Provided for non-commercial research and educational use only.
Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use.
This article was originally published in the International Encyclopedia of the Social
& Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, published by Elsevier, and the attached copy
is provided by Elsevier for the author’s benefit and for the benefit of the
author’s institution, for non-commercial research and educational use including
without limitation use in instruction at your institution, sending it to specific
colleagues who you know, and providing a copy to your institution’s administrator.
All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including
without limitation commercial reprints, selling or
licensing copies or access, or posting on open
internet sites, your personal or institution’s website or
repository, are prohibited. For exceptions, permission
may be sought for such use through Elsevier’s
permissions site at:
http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial
From Martin, J.L., Lee, M., 2015. Social Structure. In: James D. Wright
(editor-in-chief), International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences,
2nd edition, Vol 22. Oxford: Elsevier. pp. 713–718.
ISBN: 9780080970868
Copyright © 2015 Elsevier Ltd. unless otherwise stated. All rights reserved.
Elsevier
Author's personal copy
Social Structure
John L Martin and Monica Lee, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
This article is a revision of the previous edition article by F. Chazel, volume 22, pp. 1523315237, Ó 2001, Elsevier Ltd.
Abstract
Social structure is about patterns of relations. Two main families of approaches conceive these patterns differently. One, a top
down one, tends to see a global organization as stemming from a common shared culture. The second, a bottom up, pays
more attention to agglomerative processes that begin with individuals who may or may not begin with shared cultural
templates.
Social structure refers to patternings in social relations that have
some sort of obduracy. Within this general denition, there are
two primary families of more specic approaches. In the rst,
structure may be used to refer on the macro level to the
abstract organization of reciprocally dened social categories
that are seen to comprise some social whole. In the second, the
term can be used to refer to smaller scale social structures,
congurations of concrete relationships among individuals
without reference to a notion of a larger societal totality. We
organize our exposition accordingly. (We note that Porpora
(1989) in addition gave as conceptions of social structure
rst, that of Anthony Giddens, which we treat here as an
extreme form of the rst understanding of structure, and
second, relations between variables, but we have not seen any
examples of people claiming this as a denition of structure,
and we discuss this under the related heading of social systems
below.)
Structure as Abstract Relations between Social
Positions
Although all the approaches in this category link structure to
some sort of organization of positions or types that anchor
action, they differ as to the logic of the organization of the
positions that may variously be taken to be social functions,
roles, or classes.
Structure and Function
The idea of social structure was rst introduced by Herbert
Spencer (e.g., 1896[1873]: pp. 5660). At the time, the word
structure in biology referred to what we would now call
organs, sets of contiguous tissue that performed a speciable
function for the organism as a whole. Spencer argued that
society had social structures that carried out social functions.
Thus the root of the idea of social structure comes from the
organismic metaphor applied to society. This metaphor is
certainly an old one; in the Western tradition we often begin
with Plato, who (we now say) suggested that the city might be
understood as a man writ large, and thus a convenient place
for an anthropology. (In the Republic (II:368d) Plato argues
that, given that those of us with imperfect vision have an easier
time reading larger letters, we should nd a place to study the
nature of justice similarly writ large, and that is the city. From
here, he uses our interdependence to derive the need for
specic occupations, for specialization, and for trade
(369371).) Now indeed, Plato did suggest a mapping
between characteristics of persons and those of the city. Most
important, Plato made a distinction between (what might
appear to us as) cognition, emotions, and instincts. Thus in the
fourth book of the Republic (espec. x436), Plato had Socrates
demonstrate that there are three parts of the soul that have
different functions that we learn with one part of ourselves,
feel anger with another, and with yet a third desire the pleasures
of nutrition and generation. (The physical organs to which
these were taken to correspond were for many centuries taken
to be the head, the heart, and the liver, organized in a vertical
hierarchy.) So too, he argued, the city has three classes, each of
whom must do its part. Some make things (or make money,
corresponding to the appetitive), some make rules (corre-
sponding to the nous, the intellect), and some make war. These
correspond to three qualities of the good city, which should be
wise (the wisdom of the city is the wisdom of its counselors),
brave (the bravery of the city is the bravery of its ghters), and
sober (Republic, x428434). Now despite his famous emphasis
on our interdependence and even on the division of labor,
Plato did not propose an organismic model of the state, and it
seems that no such developed analogies arose in Europe until
the mass of differentiable urban occupations were no longer
associated with servile status.
With the rise of materialist views of human beings and of
society, organismic metaphors were extended into more
developed allegories: thus Hobbes (1943[1651]: pp. 8, 171,
183188, 193f., 246257) proposed correspondences in the
body politic to nerves, blood and joints, and could liken its
states of illness to pleurisy, Siamese triplets, and constipation.
But despite his categorical rejection of metaphor, Hobbess use
of the organismic language stemmed as much from his love of
pursuing a simile as from his explanatory goals. (Thus not only
is the distribution of goods analogous to nutrition, but these
good ultimately come from either the land or the sea, (the two
breasts of our common Mother), adds Hobbes (1943[1651]:
p. 189).) Certainly, Hobbes treated the organismic predicate as
one of metaphor and not as one of identity (e.g., systems may
be compared . to the similar parts of mans body (emphasis
added)), and alternated between it and others (the common-
wealth as building, as Leviathan, or as Mortall God).
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 22 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.32154-7 713
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy
Although such organismic metaphors remained popular,
we do not know of any attempt to produce a serious and
detailed exposition until Spencer. Comte (1974[1842]: 510ff)
too had advanced an organismic metaphor by applying it to the
societal division of labor, examining the laws according to
which the societal whole develops and how the whole regulates
its constituent organs. But Comtes overriding theme of whol-
ism (and his impatience to begin wholesale social reconstruc-
tion) led him to neglect a detailed consideration of the parts.
By contrast, Spencer argued that the functional needs of the
whole not only were met by the parts (like Plato), nor that there
were laws of development of the whole (like Comte), but that
structures (and functions) have their own developmental
tendencies that direct the social organisms course of develop-
ment. (Just as in the man there are structures and functions
which make possible the doings his biographer tells of, so in the
nation there are structures and functions which make possible
the doings its historian tells of; and in both cases it is with these
structures and functions, in their origin, development, and
decline, that science is concerned (Spencer, 1896[1873]:
p. 52).) Further, despite his use of the organismic metaphor,
Spencer (e.g., 1910: p. 244) always saw the functions that were
met by social structures as being, at base, functional needs of the
individuals who composed society (and not those of the social
whole apart from the individuals). Human action is funda-
mentally driven to meet human needs and wants such as
defending against enemies and obtaining food. Individuals
cooperate to fulll those ends, giving rise to structures. Thus
social structure referred to the internal organization of the social
whole arising as a by-product of the functional interdependence
of human life (a point that Malinowski was later to reiterate).
The organismic analogy developed in ways charted by
Kaufmann (1908) and Levine (1995). What was crucial for
sociology and anthropology was the duality of structure and
function that was accepted by Durkheim (most notably in The
Division of Labor) and elaborated by Radcliffe-Brown.
Like Spencer and Comte, Durkheim proposed that society is
structured according to the functions that social groups fulll in
the division of labor. But while Spencer retained an emphasis
on the ontological primacy of the individual, Durkheim unre-
servedly based his theory in the sui generis existence of social
order. He examined how the functional interdependence upon
which the division of labor is based served as societys source of
social solidarity. The most fundamental function in society is
the division of labors function of integrating and uniting the
societal organism, thereby sustaining its life (1933[1893]:
p. 11). While mechanical solidarity solidarity based on indi-
viduals similarities was the dominant foundation for social
bonds in earlier epochs, modern society, according to Dur-
kheim, is bound primarily by organic solidarity solidarity
that arises from individuals interdependence in the societal
division of labor. Differentiated social groups comprise a system
of organs (p. 132), each of which performs a specialized duty
that sustains the whole. These organs are bound to each other by
relationships of functional interdependence (pp. 83, 173),
where the survival of the whole depends on each organ per-
forming its specic duty. The more specialized the function of
an organism, the more integrated and developed the society.
This perspective was inuential in anthropology, largely
mediated by the work of Radcliffe-Brown (1952: p. 179), who
emphasized that a structure is thus to be dened as a set of
relations between entities. Further, while other theorists had
focused on a few roles as key kinship or occupation, most
notably Radcliffe-Brown (1952: 191f) argued that such
structure had to be understood as involving all such relations.
This suggested a more complete vision of an all-encompassing
and mutually consistent social structure. Strangely, sociology
tended to be inuenced by earlier work in anthropology that
drew more upon notions of kinship than social functions,
perhaps because it had clearer implications.
Structure as Role
In particular, anthropologist Ralph Linton (1936) had sug-
gested a second duality (after that of structure/function),
namely that of status and role. A status, argued Linton (1936:
p. 113) is a slot in social structure, or as he said (he used the
idea of social systems, not structures), a position in
a particular pattern. Such a position has both rights and duties
associated with it, and action in accordance with these is the
performance of a role. Thus the role is the active counterpart to
the status, the verb form as opposed to the noun. (One will
note that in English, perhaps the bulk of early terms for
common objects also have proper usage as verbs: to hammer is
to use a hammer, to water is to put water on, and so on. So too
a mother mothers, and this is a status roling.)
A number of sociologists have similarly examined social
structure as an organized set of roles. This structure was
increasingly understood by sociologists as one-half, or one-
third, of the realm of study at hand. Pitrim Sorokin (e.g., 1962)
proposed a triad of personality, society, and culture (though he is
more known for employing the latter two as a pair), and this
triad was also adopted by both his younger colleague (and
nemesis), Talcott Parsons and his graduate student, Robert
Merton. Both saw the social dimension as referring to some-
thing structural, and both paradigmatically took this to mean
the organization of social roles, thus preserving the Lintonian
duality. Parsons in particular emphasized the close mapping
between structure and culture. In Parsonss (1961) words, the
structure of social systems . consists in institutionalized
patterns of normative culture. Societal roles, in other words,
are dened by specic norms that prescribe rules for behavior.
Robert Merton (1957) also explicitly began with this
understanding of social structure, and indeed said status and
roles become concepts serving to connect culturally dened
expectations with the patterned conduct and relationships
which make up a social structure. (Parenthetically, we also
note that Merton (e.g., 1976) maintained an interest in the
emerging structuralist theories and believed them related to his
own structural approach. We return to this branch below.)
In sum, this approach to social structure tended to
emphasize culture, and see structure as, at least in the long-run
equilibrium, a nonproblematic objectivation of cultural
patterns. This priority tended to be reversed in most approaches
that drew from Marx.
Structure and Class
Now we have said that Spencer was the rst to use the term
social structure, and this is indeed true. However, Marx had
714 Social Structure
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy
used similar language, and, with Engels in The German Ideology
(Marx and Engels, 1976[18451846]: 35f), had written The
social structure and the state are continually evolving out of the
life-process of denite individuals, however, of these individ-
uals, not as they may appear in their own or other peoples
imagination, but as they actually are; i.e., as they act, produce
materially, and hence as they work under de nite material
limits, presuppositions, and conditions independent of their
will. The term translated as social structure, namely gesell-
schaftliche Gliederung (Werke, 3:25) carries more connotations
of organization or arrangement, and somewhat fewer of
a construction. Marxs conception in its most general is to
emphasize what he called (in the Theses on Feuerbach) the
ensemble of societal relations (Werke 3:7).
The social relations of paramount interest to Marx were
economic ones, more specically, the social relations of
production. These relations appear in juridical form as property
relations, but in social form as the relations between classes. It
is this set of relations that Marx argued constituted the
economic structure of society; the superstructure erected on
top of this includes legal, political, and ideological formations
that have some degree of homology to the underlying
economic structure (see Marxism). Thus as in the previous
conception of social structure, we have a close duality between
cultural understandings and patterns of relations. But while the
rst conception privileged the cultural realm as having
explanatory priority, here it is the pattern of relations that must
be understood rst.
Structure as Culture as Structure
These conceptions tend to establish a duality between what
ones position in structure is, and what one does; we have seen
that in the Lintonian and Parsonian versions, this implies
a duality between social structure and aspects of culture. This
was taken to its logical vanishing point in the work of Anthony
Giddens. Giddens decided to claim as structure in social
systems rules and resources, arguing (e.g., 1979: pp. 6466)
that structure exists only as the structural indeed, the struc-
turing properties of a social system. (Here he seems to have
been inuenced by the conception of structuralism discussed
below.) Although intellectually pleasing, by placing a heap of
social structure in the heads of the actors (in the form of rules),
Giddens, wittingly or unwittingly, sent social theory careening
down a hill in which structure and culture would end up being
not simply dual, but indistinguishable. This was associated
with further confusions.
For whether it is the expectation that the duties of the
younger sister include looking after aging parents, or it is the
class relation that the proletariat does not own the means of
production but instead sells labor power, social structure was
easily assimilated to constraint and restriction of individuals.
As a result, especially in Britain, there arose a conviction that
social action could be analyzed as a two-part beast, one part the
structural constraint and the other, agency. Unlike the seem-
ingly homologous division of the self by Mead into the me
(including, what they expect me to do) and the I (what I
actually did), here most conceptions made a differentiation
between those actions that reproduced structure (and hence had
no valid claim to agency) and those that challenged,
transformed, or at least grumbled about the structure. But with
the transition from (1) structure being dened as organized
relations to (2) structure being de ned by its pernicious effects,
we leave the realm of sociology, and hence do not pursue this
approach further. Instead, we briey indicate how these top-
down conceptions of social structure inuenced and then were
inuenced by the development of two related concepts.
Continuities
Systems Theory
This conception of social structure inuenced the development
of two relatively coherent schools of thought, treated separately
in this volume. The rst is systems theory ( see Systems Theory),
which also started with the organismic metaphor (indeed,
when Hobbes spoke of social systems, he was using the then-
current term system for organ). Modern systems theory, the
rise of which is often assumed to begin with Ludwig von
Bertalanffys (1968) work in the 1940s, explores the regulari-
ties that emerge when sets of elements whether physiological,
environmental, or social assume such a form that they
become self-regulating. In other words, they maintain them-
selves within a range of possibilities (a state space) through
self-correcting feedback mechanisms. In the context of social
science, systems theory explores how societies remain stable
and functioning as their constituent parts cooperate and adapt
to one another. What is important for us is the effects that this
had on notions of social structure.
Talcott Parsons rst popularized a systems approach to the
study of social structure in The Social System (1951). He went on
to propose four systemic necessities basic functions that
systems must perform in order to maintain their existence as
key to understanding the organization and development of
societies. Parsons tended to propose subsystems that were
dened wholly functionally (and not structurally), and to
examine the media that various subsystems used to order their
relations or to interact with other subsystems. To the extent that
such systems thinking was taken seriously, it tended to lessen
interest in social structure as such (an emphasis preserved by
Merton, who maintained an ambivalent relation to the idea of
systems).
A further divergence of systems and structural thinking came
with the work of Luhmann. Once mentored by Parsons, Niklas
Luhmann developed a rival approach to systems theory whose
core is communication rather than action. Humans are not
coordinated into action systems but systems of observing and
sense making. Actors confront an external environment in which
massive amounts of information circulate. As they observe, select
out, and make sense of, bits of information, the system is
constituted (1996: p. 24). By observing the environment, the
observer distinguishes between himself and the environment,
and this act of distinction brings the observer into being. What is
essential for us are three points: rst, the components here are
acts of communication, not social relationships. Second, there is
a self-organization (autopoiesis) of this set of communications
that may be largely decoupled from the needs of organic indi-
viduals. Third, such systems are more than a mere analytical tool
that elucidates societal processes; rather, systems exist (1995:
p. 12). Thus although Luhmann did argue that the major social
subsystems corresponded to well-understood realms (which he
Social Structure 715
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy
successively explored: law, art, politics, religion, economy and
education), we must be prepared for functional sub-sub-systems
that are potentially divorced from needs of individuals and even
from the role structure.
Structuralism
The second offshoot is the line of thought termed structur-
alism (see Structuralism). This tradition in many ways
branched off of Comte and Durkheim; although it is generally
understood to have originated with the structural linguistics of
Ferdinand de Saussure, Saussure himself was inuenced by
Durkheims Comtean division between statics and dynamics.
Saussure argued that words meanings arise not from an
intrinsic quality that links them to the phenomena they
represent, but from the systematic distinctions that differentiate
them (as signs or sounds) from one another in a linguistic
system (Saussure 1983[1916]). (Words are purely differential
and dened not by their positive content but negatively by their
relations with the other terms of the system. Their most precise
characteristic is in being what the others are not (Saussure
[1916]1983: p. 651).) This approach was then elaborated in
the science of phonology by Roman Jakobson, who examined
how the organization of sounds into systems conveys linguistic
meaning. In all cases, structuralism proposed two types of
relations (syntax/system, metonymy/metaphor, afne/cognate)
that, brought into the realm of social structure, suggested
attention both to empirical relations of interaction (on the one
hand) and relations of structural equivalence functional
substitutability (on the other).
Claude Levi-Strauss (1969[1949]) applied these structur-
alist principles to the study of social structure in The Elementary
Structures of Kinship. Here Levi-Strauss examined the structural
logics that organize complex patterns of kin relationships by
understanding them as formal laws of transfers (as a marriage
may be seen as the transfer of a daughter (or son) from one
lineage to another). Levi-Strauss went on to focus on cognitive
structures, but the encouraging results of this work on kinship
led to a common enthusiasm for structure in the social sense
as well. There were relatively few rigorously structuralist
approaches to social structure, however, though we discuss one
below.
Structure as Patterns of Concrete Interaction
A second major approach divorces the idea of structure from
the abstract notion of an organized society. Instead, it sees
structure as concrete patterns of interaction among individual
persons that may exhibit greater or lesser levels of organization.
These social relationships are also attached to cultural mean-
ings of various sorts for instance, subjective orientations or
cultural narratives. But these approaches tend to be more
bottom up, and suggest a plurality of structural elements that
may overlap with or without mutual reinforcement.
Structure as Forms of Interaction
This general approach was largely rooted in the work of Georg
Simmel. Like Durkheim and Marx, Simmel saw society (or
social life) as fundamentally about relations among persons.
But he eschewed the structural functionalists presupposition
that society is divided into subparts organized into a (more or
less) functional whole or system. Indeed, in his rst major
work, Simmel (1890: p. 13) challenges the organismic view of
society, which sees society as an absolute unity. Rather, this
concept of society is only secondary to the real interaction of
its parts, only a result of it as much in reality as in concep-
tualization.’‘The social organism, speaking loosely, must be
understood as but a summary expression of the interaction of
the parts, and it is only these parts individuals that have
vitality. Rather than the process of differentiation leading to
simpler and more unitarily dened individuals (as in Dur-
kheims conception), the true differentiation is internal to
individuals who straddle multiple social roles.
As a result, Simmel decoupled the concept of structure from
social groups functional roles in society, and proposed
a formal sociology focused on patterns of interaction among
individuals. These interactions continuously broken off and
remade do not necessarily amount to actual organization
(1992[1908]: p. 33), nor must they conform to the routines of
societys service organs (Simmel, 1897). Thus, Society for
Simmel is social interaction among persons continuously
making connections and breaking them off and making them
again, a perpetual owing and pulsing that unites individuals,
even when it does not amount to actual organization (1992
[1908]: 33). Social life consists of the living interactions,
constantly being made and remade, that pulse beneath and
beyond their service organs (
Simmel, 1897). The regularity of
these interactions comes from their being stamped from
a limited set of forms.
This sociology of forms has been appealed to by some
network researchers as an aegis for their own efforts. However,
despite his focus on formal patterns like the dyad and the triad
(actually terms supplied by his translator), Simmels use of
form had a somewhat different meaning than a geometrical
structure. Hoping to extend a neo-Kantian approach to social
life, as he had previously attempted for the study of history,
Simmel meant to uncover the a prioris for social interaction,
which he considered forms. Here he certainly meant to draw on
Kants idea of forms, quite possibly interpreted in the Platonic
way of Hermann Cohen, as something structured in the
subjectivity of actors not a pattern of relationships itself.
While purely geometric abstractions may be useful sociological
tools, they cannot be separated from the complex subjective
orientations from which they tend to emerge. These objective
and subjective elements coalesce in ideal typical forms of
sociation (Vergesellschaftung): e.g., exchange, conict, and
super- and subordination.
Most important for the science of social structure was that
Simmel, by not proposing a partition (or multiple partitions) of
society into subparts bound by relations, was able to see
structure as shifting patterns of interaction between individual
persons and thereby frame structural analysis as a conceptual
tool that could be applied to different types of connections. As
he (1955[1922]) explained in The Intersection of Social Circles,an
individual may stand simultaneously in multiple social groups
that overlap with each other at the site of that individual. Society
is a web of relationships that is not organized into a unied and
harmonious set of structures but into multiple overlapping,
often uncoordinated, and sometimes conicting, ones.
716 Social Structure
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy
Structure as Congurations of Individuals
Thisline of research was continued by Leopold von Wiese (1932),
in his theory of relations and his theory of social congurations
(soziale Gebilde). Von Wieses work was freely translated by
Howard Becker, who rendered Gebilde as plurality pattern. Von
Wiesescongurations or structures were ensembles of social
relationships that had a particular form: he argued that there were
three main types of congurations: masses, groups, and corporate
bodies. These were structures, generally composed of other
structures, that were somewhat farther from the individual than
their component structures and consequently more abstracted.
(Sorokins(1962)own approach was similar in many ways,
emphasizing the components of social organization as opposed
to beginning with functional requirements.) The somewhat
exciting aspect of von Wieses work was the implication that one
could begin with social relationships and scale upward, rst to
simple congurations composed of relationships, and then larger
structures. This general approach has been used by Tilly (1998),
Martin (2009),andMartin and Lee (2010).
Structure as Stories
This type of approach may seem to have a great deal in
common with the structural approach of Harrison White
(1992), who was concerned with the question of how social
formations emerge. Whites rst book was a recasting of Levi-
Straussian kinship structures using permutation matrices. He
then applied this rigorous structuralist understanding of social
structure to other types of social structure in a pair of important
papers, the rst of which (White et al., 1976) was very inu-
ential for social networks (see below); although the second
(Boorman and White, 1976) was more theoretically central, it
was more methodologically challenging and hence less inu-
ential. (This line of work was continued by Breiger and Pattison
(e.g., 1986), among others.)
White went on to formulate a more general approach to
social organization, and here he drew more heavily on S.F.
Nadels (1957) perspective with its cultural grounding, which
became clear in Whites magnum opus, where he posited
a strict duality between structural form and cultural narratives.
Structural ties are bound by common identities. Each tie exists
both as a pair of individuals, as well as an identity a story
about the basis of the ties solidarity that provides it continuity.
Small structures like dyads concatenate to create larger ones as
ties mesh with stories (2008: p. 27). The conversations that
take place in ties, the shared beliefs or understandings that bind
them, link up to those of other ties, presenting the opportunity
for those ties to concatenate into larger structures.
A somewhat related approach is seen in Ronald Burts
(1982) Structural Theory of Action, though the focus on action
takes him more to the Parsonian legacy of a dialogue with
economic theories of action. As with White, we start with
a focus on the actor who sees social structure sometimes as if it
were a jungle gym to be climbed, and sometimes as if it were an
undergrowth to be hacked away with a machete. Even more
than in the previous understandings, the duality of cultural and
structural understandings is one that in no way requires an
overarching order; rather, local ordering principles may
emerge, but even when they do, skilled actors may choose to
crack them.
Social Structure and Social Networks
As the discussion in the previous section makes clear, this
approach to social structure often dovetailed, inspired, or
turned into social networks research (see Social Networks).
Scholarship on social networks focuses on the relationships
between concrete actors rather than individuals, groups, or
roles. Although the foundational theoretical works in social
networks research (e.g., Barnes, 1954) envisioned the network
as sprawling, connecting, and all-encompassing form, and
hence diametrically opposed to the conventional ideas of well-
nested social sub-sub-systems and/or groups, networks have
often been understood as being a skeletal structure that should
reproduce the outlines of social structure conventionally
understood. This is, of course, an empirical question, but the
challenges to mounting a full-scale social network survey of
a population in order to determine the relation of networks to
role structures remain daunting.
Conclusion
Social structure ha s proved one of the most confusing theo-
retical terms in our lexicon; it tends to be among the most
abstract of our concepts, but has implications of solidity. It
often seem s to connote constraint o f individual actions, but is
itself nothing but a set of actions. It is regularly counterposed
to culture, but just as regularly appears to be simply the
second side of the same coin as culture. Perhaps the best that
can be said is that it appears to be an idea we cannot do
without.
See also: Action, Theories of Social; Class: Social; Exchange:
Social; Institutions; Interactionism, Symbolic; Luhmanns
Social Systems: Meaning, Autopoiesis, and Interpenetration;
Macrosociology-Microsociology; Marxism in Contemporary
Sociology; Power in Society; Social Networks; Sociological
Theory; Status and Role: Structural Aspects; Structuralism.
Bibliography
Barnes, John, 1954. Class and committees in a Norwegian Island Parish. Human
Relations 7, 3958.
Boorman, Scott A., White, Harrison C., 1976. Social structure from multiple networks,
II. Role structures. American Journal of Sociology 81, 13851446.
Breiger, Ronald L., Pattison, Phillipa E., 1986. Cumulated social roles: the duality of
persons and their algebras. Social Networks 8, 215256.
Burt, Ronald S., 1982. Toward a Structural Theory of Action. Academic Press,
New York.
Comte, Auguste, 1974[1842]. The Positive Philosophy. Freely Condensed and Edited
by Harriet Martineu. AMS Press, New York.
Durkheim, Emile, 1933[1893]. The Division of Labor in Society (G. Simpson, Trans.).
Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois.
Durkheim, Emile, 1938[1895]. The Rules of Sociological Method (S. Solovay,
J.H. Mueller, Trans.). The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois.
Giddens, Anthony, 1979. Central Problems in Social Theory. University of California
Press, Berkeley.
Hobbes, Thomas, 1943[1651]. Leviathan. The Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Kaufmann, Erich, 1908. Über den Begriff des Organismus in der Staatslehre des 19.
Jahrhunderts. Carl Winter, Heidelberg.
Levine, Donald N., 1995. The organism metaphor in sociology. Social Research 62,
239265.
Social Structure 717
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy
Levi-Strauss, Claude, 1969[1949]. The Elementary Structures of Kinship (J.H. Bell,
J.R. von Sturmer, R. Needham, Trans.). Beacon Press, Boston.
Linton, Ralph, 1936. The Study of Man. Appleton-Century-Crofts, New York.
Luhmann, Niklas, 1995[1984]. Social Systems. Stanford University Press, Stanford.
Luhmann, Niklas, 1996. The Reality of Mass Media. Polity Press, Cambridge.
Martin, John Levi, 2009. Social Structures. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Martin, John Levi, Lee, Monica, 2010. Wie entstehen große sozialen Strukturen? In:
Fuhse, Jan, Mützel, Sophie (Eds.), Relationale Soziologie: Zur kulturellen Wende
der Netzwerkforschung. VS Verlag, Wiesbaden, pp. 117136.
Marx, Karl, Engels, Frederick, 1976[18451846]. The German ideology. In: Collected
Works, vol. 5. International Publishers, New York.
Merton, Robert K., 1957. The role-set: problems in sociological theory. The British
Journal of Sociology 8, 106120.
Merton, Robert K., 1976. Sociological Ambivalence and Other Essays. The Free Press,
New York.
Nadel, S.F., 1957. The Theory of Social Structure. The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois.
Parsons, Talcott, 1951. The Social System. The Free Press, New York.
Parsons, Talcott, 1961. An outline of the social system. In: Parsons, Talcott,
Shils, Edward A., Naegle, Kaspar D., Pitts, Jesse R. (Eds.), Theories of Society,
2 vols. Simon & Schuster, The Free Press, New York, pp. 3079.
Porpora, Douglas V., 1989. Four concepts of social structure. Journal for the Theory of
Social Behaviour 19, 195211.
Radcliffe-Brown, A.R., 1952. Structure and Function in Primitive Society. Cohen and
West, London.
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 1983[1916]. Course in General Lingusitics. Open Court, Peru,
Illinois.
Simmel, Georg, 1890. Über Soziale Differenzierung. Duncker & Humblot, Leipzig.
Simmel, Georg, 1897. The persistence of social groups: I. American Journal of
Sociology 3, 662698.
Simmel, Georg, 1950[1908]. Soziologie: Untersuchung uber die Formen der Verge-
sellschaftung. In: Wolff, Kurt H. (Ed.), The Sociology of Georg Simmel (K.H. Wolff,
Trans.). The Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois.
Simmel, Georg, 1955[1922]. The web of group-afliations. Translation of Die Kreuzung
Sozialer Kreise, pp. 305344 of Soziologie, by Reinhard Bendix, appearing as 127
195 in Conict and the Web of Group Afliations. Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois.
Simmel, Georg, 1992[1908]. Sociologie: Untersuchungen über die Formen der Ver-
gesellschaftung. In: Rammstedt, O. (Ed.), Georg Simmel Gesamtausgabe, vol. 11.
Suhrkamp, Frankfurt.
Sorokin, Pitrim A., 1962. Society, Culture and Personality. Cooper Square Publishers,
New York.
Spencer, Herbert , 1896[1873]. The Study of Sociology. Appleton, New York.
Spencer, Herbert, 1910. The Principles of Sociology, vol. II. D. Appleton & Company,
New York.
Spencer, Herbert , 1915. First Principles. Williams and Norgate, London.
Tilly, Charles, 1998. Durable Inequality. University of California Press, Berkeley.
von Bertalanffy, Ludwig, 1968. General Systems Theory. George Braziller, New York.
von Wiese, Leopold, 1932. Systematic Sociology on the Basis of the Beziehungslehre
and Gebildelehre. Translated and Amplied by Howard Becker. John Wiley & Sons,
New York.
White, Harrison C., 1963. An Anatomy of Kinship. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New
Jersey.
White, Harrison C., 1992. Identity a nd Contro l. Princeto n Unive rsity Press,
Princeton.
White, Harrison C., Boorman, S.A., Breiger, Ronald L., 1976. Social structure from
multiple networks. I. Blockmodels of roles and positions. American Journal of
Sociology 81, 730779.
718 Social Structure
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Second Edition, 2015, 713–718
Author's personal copy